Time travel. It’s something that exists in a narrow region between science and fantasy. Maybe it’s theoretically possible, maybe it’s nothing more than wishful thinking.
Who knows.
But in the realm of fiction, anything can happen.
Time Machine Backup
Apple Time Machine Review. Time Machine is the go-to backup solution for most Apple fans, but the cloud offers just too many benefits to recommend this prepackaged, hardware-based program. An ‘Astral Projection Time Travel Machine Helmet Psychotronic Technology’, for $129.95. (Photo: Ebay) The urge to travel through time is irresistible. It is, in fact, timeless: H.G.
So here’s a list of my top ten fictional time machines, in a somewhat specific order.
10. The Ancient Japanese Scepter
“Do you think they had pizza back then?”
Oh, that’s an odd one. Teenage Mutant Ninja Turtles III was terrible. I didn’t completely realize it at the time (I was young), but it just never set well with me, not compared to the first two films.
Later, I’d come to understand why (thank you Angry Video Game Nerd), but you know what?
I still think the design of the ancient Japanese scepter is very cool. It’s what transports the turtles back in time to feudal Japan, where they…do stuff. I don’t remember too much past that, honestly. But the scepter gets a comfortable position on my list.
9. The Backstep Sphere
“Someday I’m gonna form a chrononauts’ union…”
If you’ve never seen the television series Seven Days, here’s a brief synopsis:
A secret branch of the NSA retrieves the wreckage of the 1947 Roswell, New Mexico UFO crash and uses it to create a time machine, called the Chronosphere (or Backstep Sphere).
Thing is, the machine’s fuel is limited, so it can only travel back seven days. So, whenever something bad happens, chrononaut Frank Parker jumps into the machine and travels one week back in time. Each episode consists of Parker heading back and attempting to, well, fix things…even though he’s always the only one aware that a backstep has occurred.
It’s a really cool show, and the Chronosphere would rank higher if I could buy the series on DVD. You heard me.
8. The Epoch
“The past is dead. It was all just a dream…”
What? A time machine from a video game? What the…
Well, Chrono Trigger for the Super Nintendo is regarded as one of the best RPGs ever made, and it’s got a cool story: when an accident at the Millenial Fair sends one of Crono’s friends back in time, it’s up to him to travel back and rescue her. But wait, there’s more: they wind up visiting the future, only to find that the world has been ravaged by the evil Lavos.
So they journey to the End of Time, acquire the time machine Epoch (also called the Wings of Time, which you can see above), and it’s off to the past to prevent Lavos from gaining power and destroying the world.
There’s another popular SNES RPG that involves time travel, but maybe we’ll talk about that one later…
7. The TARDIS
“…it’s more like a big ball of wibbly-wobbly, timey-wimey…stuff.”
Something old, something new, something borrowed, something blue…at least, I think that’s how it goes.
Bigger on the inside than on the outside, the TARDIS serves as The Doctor’s vehicle through time and space in the television series Doctor Who.
TARDIS stands for Time and Relative Dimension in Space, by the way, and it looks like a police box because its environmental-blendy-thingy glitched out. It happens.
Really, everything about Doctor Who is pretty cool. I like how it can go from whimsical to dramatic on the turn of a dime. Who’s my favorite Doctor? I’m gonna have to go with David Tennant.
6. The Phone Booth
“Billy, you are dealing with the oddity of time travel with the greatest of ease.”
Ah, Bill & Ted’s Excellent Adventure.
Maybe it’s a slight rip-off of the TARDIS, maybe it’s not, but Ted “Theodore” Logan and Bill S. Preston, Esquire like to do their history research using a time traveling telephone booth, bestowed upon them by their temporal guide, Rufus.
With it, Bill & Ted take an (ahem) excellent adventure to various points in history, picking up such legendary figures as Socrates (that’s So-crates) and Joan of Arc. They even visit the future…where they learn their music will one day lead to world peace.
5. The Time Turner
“Mysterious thing, time. Powerful, and when meddled with, dangerous.”
Oh, yeah, Harry Potter. Weren’t expecting that, were you?
Harry Potter and the Prisoner of Azkaban was the first Harry Potter movie I ever saw (well, the first one I ever paid attention to). As some kind of twist of fate, I ended up seeing it opening night in Orlando. People were dressed up as the characters, wearing long robes and wielding wands, and I thought, “Well, this is weird.”
But surprise, surprise…I thought the movie was pretty good, and the time travel themes were cool, too.
The movie specifically plays with causality loops — whatever happens was always going to happen. And the Time Turner…like a watch, its user must “wind-up” the device, with a single turn equaling one hour back in time.
4. The Ocarina Of Time
“The flow of time is always cruel…its speed seems different for each person, but no one can change it…”
In The Legend of Zelda: Ocarina of Time for Nintendo 64, Link uses a mystical ocarina to reach the sacred realm within the Temple of Time, where he travels seven years into the future.
Time Machine Movie
In the game’s sequel, Majora’s Mask, he uses the same ocarina to repeat a three day cycle over and over again, until he can find a way to stop the mischievous (and possessed) skull kid from destroying the world.
Both games stand as two of my all-time favorites. Their somewhat dark aesthetics, music, and time travel themes — not to mention the impact they had on me as a kid — to this day stand the test of time…
3. The Box
“Man, are you hungry? I haven’t eaten since later this afternoon.”
If time travel ever becomes a reality — and if any crackpot scientists accidentally build a working time machine — I imagine it’ll be a lot like the strange boxes found in Primer.
The movie may seem like a convoluted mess the first time you watch it, but it’s actually the most compelling time travel film I’ve ever seen.
Without giving anything away, the two protagonists, Aaron and Abe, can only travel so far back as when the machine was built. As the movie progresses, we see the bizarre effects that time traveling has on not only the timeline, but on personal relationships…
2. The DeLorean Time Machine
“The way I see it, if you’re gonna build a time machine into a car, why not do it with some style?”
Perhaps the most obvious (and famous) time machine on this list, the DeLorean time machine from Back to the Future is iconic.
Doctor Emmett Brown “discovered” time travel after he slipped and hit his head on his bathroom sink (while hanging a clock, no less) on November 5, 1955. That’s when he had the idea for the flux capacitor, the device that makes time travel possible.
He then spent years working on the invention, until finally testing it out in 1985 at the Twin Pines Mall parking lot. Just crank that baby to 88 mph and, well, you know the rest.
You’d think this would be #1 on my list, really, given that Back to the Future is one of my all-time favorite movies. But no…there is another…
1. The Power Of The Mind
“Come back to me.”
Based on Richard Matheson’s novel Bid Time Return, Somewhere In Time tells the peculiar story of Richard Collier. After seeing a photograph of the beautiful Elise McKenna at Michigan’s Grand Hotel, Collier becomes obsessed with the prospect of time traveling to 1912 and meeting her.
He eventually accomplishes this very act through self-hypnosis…the power of the mind.
It’s funny, really, because this movie is what brought me to the John Titor story in the first place, and really sparked my interest in time travel. As soon as I finished watching it, I hit the Internet to see if there was any information out there about time travel and…well, there was and there is.
But it’s not just that. I found Somewhere In Time genuinely haunting, and I’ve only seen it once. While there are differences between the film and the novel (the novel leaves the reality of the time travel ambiguous), something about it feels…possible.
Like lucid dreaming, which can feel very authentic…if only you can hold on to the illusion. Or perhaps time traveling in our minds is very real, indeed.
So there you go. That’s my list. Have any favorite time machines I didn’t mention? Share them in the comments!
Recent years have seen a growing consensus in the philosophical community that the grandfather paradox and similar logical puzzles donot preclude the possibility of time travel scenarios that utilize spacetimes containing closed timelike curves. At the same time, physicists, who for half a century acknowledged that the general theory of relativity is compatible with such spacetimes, have intensely studied the question whether the operation of a time machine would be admissible in the context of the same theory and of its quantum cousins. A time machine is a device which brings about closed timelike curves—and thus enables time travel—wherenone would have existed otherwise. The physics literature contains various no-go theorems for time machines, i.e., theorems which purport to establish that, under physically plausible assumptions, the operation of a time machine is impossible. We conclude that for the time being there exists no conclusive no-go theorem against time machines. The character of the material covered in this article makesit inevitable that its content is of a rather technical nature. We contend, however, that philosophers should nevertheless be interestedin this literature for at least two reasons. First, the topic of timemachines leads to a number of interesting foundations issues in classical and quantum theories of gravity; and second, philosophers can contribute to the topic by clarifying what it means for a device to count as a time machine, by relating the debate to other concerns such as Penrose’s cosmic censorship conjecture and the fate of determinism in general relativity theory, and by eliminating a numberof confusions regarding the status of the paradoxes of time travel. The present article addresses these ambitions in as non-technical a manner as possible, and the reader is referred to the relevant physics literature for details.
1. Introduction: time travel vs. time machine
The topic of time machines is the subject of a sizable and growing physics literature, some of which has filtered down to popular and semi-popular presentations.[1] The issues raised by this topic are largely oblique, if not orthogonal, to those treated in the philosophical literature on time travel.[2] Most significantly, the so-called paradoxes of time travel do not play a substantial role in the physics literature on time machines. This literature equates the possibility of time travel with the existence of closed timelike curves (CTCs) or worldlines for materialparticles that are smooth, future-directed timelike curves with self-intersections.[3] Since time machines designate devices which bring about the existenceof CTCs and thus enable time travel, the paradoxes of time travel areirrelevant for attempted “no-go” results for time machines because these results concern what happens before the emergence of CTCs.[4] This, in our opinion, is fortunate since the paradoxes of time travelare nothing more than a crude way of bringing out the fact that the application of familiar local laws of relativistic physics to a spacetime background which contains CTCs typically requires that consistency constraints on initial data must be met in order for a local solution of the laws to be extendable to a global solution. Thenature and status of these constraints is the subject of ongoing discussion. We will not try to advance the discussion of this issue here;[5] rather, our aim is to acquaint the reader with the issues addressed in the physics literature on time machines and to connect them with issues in the philosophy of space and time and, more generally, with issues in the foundations of physics.
Paradox mongers can be reassured in that if a paradox is lost in shifting the focus from time travel itself to time machines, then a paradox is also gained: if it is possible to operate a time machine device that produces CTCs, then it is possible to alter the structureof spacetime such that determinism fails; but by undercutting determinism, the time machine undercuts the claim that it is responsible for producing CTCs. But just as the grandfather paradox is a crude way of making a point, so this new paradox is a crude way of indicating that it is going to be difficult to specify what it means to be a time machine. This is a task that calls not for paradoxmongering but for scientifically informed philosophizing. The presentarticle will provide the initial steps of this task and will indicatewhat remains to be done. But aside from paradoxes, the main payoff ofthe topic of time machines is that it provides a quick route to the heart of a number of foundations problems in classical general relativity theory and in attempts to produce a quantum theory of gravity by combining general relativity and quantum mechanics. We will indicate the shape of some of these problems here, but will refer the interested reader elsewhere for technical details.
There are at least two distinct general notions of time machines, which we will call Wellsian and Thornian for short.In The Time Machine, H. G. Wells (1931) described what has become science fiction’s paradigmatic conception of a time machine: the intrepid operator fastens her seat belt, dials the target date—past or future—into the counter, throws a lever, andsits back while time rewinds or fast forwards until the target date is reached. We will not broach the issue of whether or not a Wellsiantime machine can be implemented within a relativistic spacetime framework. For, as will soon become clear, the time machines which have recently come into prominence in the physics literature are of an utterly different kind. This second kind of time machine was originally proposed by Kip Thorne and his collaborators (see Morris and Thorne 1988; Morris, Thorne, and Yurtsever 1988). These articles considered the possibility that, without violating the laws of general relativistic physics, an advanced civilization might manipulate concentrations of matter-energy so as to produce CTCs where none would have existed otherwise. In their example, the production of “wormholes” was used to generate the required spacetime structure. But this is only one of the ways in which a time machine might operate, and in what follows any device which affects the spacetime structure in such a way that CTCs result will be dubbed a Thornian time machine. We will only be concerned with this variety of time machine, leaving the Wellsian variety to science fiction writers. This will disappoint the aficionados of science fiction since Thornian time machines do not have the magical ability to transport the would-be time traveler to the past of the events that constitute the operation of the time machine. For those more interested in science than in science fiction, this loss is balanced by the gain in realism and the connection to contemporary research in physics.
In Sections 2 and 3 we investigate the circumstances under which it is plausible to see a Thornian time machine at work. The main difficulty lies in specifying the conditions needed to make sense of the notion that the time machine “produces” or is “responsible for” the appearances of CTCs. We argue that at present there is no satisfactory resolution of this difficulty and, thus, that the topic of time machines in a general relativistic setting is somewhat ill-defined. This fact does not prevent progress from being made on the topic; for if one’s aim is to establish no-go results for time machines it suffices to identify necessary conditions for the operation of a time machine and then to prove, under suitable hypotheses about what is physically possible, that it is not physically possible to satisfy said necessary conditions. In Section 4 we review various no-go results which depend only on classical general relativity theory. Section 5 surveys results that appeal to quantum effects. Conclusions are presented in Section 6.
2. What is a (Thornian) time machine? Preliminaries
The setting for the discussion is a general relativisticspacetime ((mathcal{M},g_{ab})) where (mathcal{M}) is a differentiable manifold and(g_{ab}) is a Lorentz signature metric defined on allof (mathcal{M}). The central issue addressed in thephysics literature on time machines is whether in this general settingit is physically possible to operate a Thornian time machine. Thisissue is to be settled by proving theorems about the solutions to theequations that represent what are taken to be physical laws operatingin the general relativistic setting—or at least this is so oncethe notion of a Thornian time machine has been explicated.Unfortunately, no adequate and generally accepted explication thatlends itself to the required mathematical proofs is to be found in theliterature. This is neither surprising nor deplorable. Mathematicalphysicists do not wait until some concept has received its finalexplication before trying to prove theorems about it; indeed, theprocess of theorem proving is often an essential part of conceptualclarification. The moral is well illustrated by the history of theconcept of a spacetime singularity in general relativity where thisconcept received its now canonical definition only in the process ofproving the Penrose-Hawking-Geroch singularity theorems, which came atthe end of a decades long dispute over the issue of whether spacetimesingularities are a generic feature of solutions to Einstein’sgravitational field equations.[6]However, this is not to say that philosophers interested in timemachines should simply wait until the dust has settled in the physicsliterature; indeed, the physics literature could benefit fromdeployment of the analytical skills that are the stock in trade ofphilosophy. For example, the paradoxes of time travel and the fate oftime machines are not infrequently confused in the physics literature,and as will become evident below, subtler confusions abound aswell.
The question of whether a Thornian time machine—a device that produces CTCs—can be seen to be at work only makes sense if thespacetime has at least three features: temporal orientability, a definite time orientation, and a causally innocuous past. In order tomake the notion of a CTC meaningful, the spacetime must be temporally orientable (i.e., must admit a consistent time directionality), and one of the two possible time orientations has tobe singled out as giving the direction of time.[7] Non-temporal orientability is not really an obstacle since if a givengeneral relativistic spacetime is not temporally orientable, a spacetime that is everywhere locally the same as the given spacetime and is itself temporally orientable can be obtained by passing to a covering spacetime.[8] How to justify the singling out of one of the two possible orientations as future pointing requires a solution to the problem ofthe direction of time, a problem which is still subject to lively debate (see Callender 2001). But for present purposes we simply assume that a temporal orientation has been provided. A CTC is then (by definition) a parameterized closed spacetime curve whose tangent is everywhere a future-pointing timelike vector. A CTC can be thoughtof as the world line of some possible observer whose life history is linearly ordered in the small but not in the large: the observer has a consistent experience of the “next moment,” and the “next,” etc., but eventually the “next moment” brings her back to whatever event she regards as the starting point.
As for the third condition—a causally innocuous past—the question of the possibility of operating a device that produces CTCs presupposes that there is a time before which no CTCs existed. Thus, Gödel spacetime, so beloved of the time travel literature, is not a candidate for hosting a Thornian time machine since through every point in this spacetime there is a CTC. We make this third condition precise by requiring that the spacetime admits a globaltime slice (Sigma) (i.e., a spacelike hypersurface without edges);[9] that (Sigma) is two-sided and partitions (mathcal{M}) into three parts—(Sigma) itself,the part of (mathcal{M}) on the past side of (Sigma) and the part of (mathcal{M}) on the future side of (Sigma)—and that there are no CTCs that lie on the past side of(Sigma). The first two clauses of this requirement together entail that the time slice (Sigma) is a partial Cauchy surface, i.e., (Sigma) is a time slice that is not intersected more than once by any future-directed timelike curve.[10]
Now suppose that the state on a partial Cauchy surface (Sigma_0) with no CTCs to its past is to be thought of as giving a snapshot of the universe at a moment before the machine is turned on. The subsequent realization of a Thornian time machine scenario requires that the chronology violating region (V subseteq mathcal{M}), the region of spacetime traced out by CTCs,[11] is non-null and lies to the future of (Sigma_0). The fact that (V ne varnothing) does not lead to any consistency constraints on initial data on (Sigma_0) since, by hypothesis, (Sigma_0) is not intersected more than once by any timelike curve, and thus, insofar as the so-called paradoxes of time travel are concerned with such constraints, the paradoxes do notarise with respect to (Sigma_0). But by the same token, theoption of traveling back into the past of (Sigma_0) is ruled out by the set up as it has been sketched so far, since otherwise (Sigma_0) would not be a partial Cauchy surface. This just goes to underscore the point made above that the fans of science fiction stories of time machines will not find the present context of discussion broad enough to encompass their vision of how time machines should operate; they may now stop reading this article and return to their novels.
As a concrete example of these concepts, consider the ((1 + 1))-dimensional Misner spacetime (see Figure 1) which exhibits some of the causal features of Taub-NUT spacetime, a vacuum solution to Einstein’s gravitational field equations. It satisfies all three of the conditions discussed above. It is temporally orientable, and a time orientation has been singled out—the shading in the figure indicates the future lobes of thelight cones. To the past of the partial Cauchy surface (Sigma_0) lies the Taub region where the causal structure of spacetime is as bland as can be desired. But to the future of (Sigma_0) the light cones begin to “tip over,” and eventually the tipping results in CTCs in the NUT region.
The issue that must be faced now is what further conditions must be imposed in order that the appearance of CTCs to the future of (Sigma_0) can be attributed to the operation of a time machine. Not surprisingly, the answer depends not just on the structure of the spacetime at issue but also on the physical laws that govern the evolution of the spacetime structure. If one adopts the attitude that the label “time machine” is to be reserved for devices that operate within a finite spatial range for afinite stretch of time, then one will want to impose requirements to assure that what happens in a compact region of spacetime lying on orto the future of (Sigma_0) is responsible for the CTCs. Or one could be more liberal and allow the would-be time machine to be spread over an infinite space. We will adopt the more liberal stance since it avoids various complications while still sufficing to elicitkey points. Again, one could reserve the label “time machine” for devices that manipulate concentrations of mass-energy in some specified ways. For example, based on Gödel spacetime—where matter is everywhere rotating and a CTC passes through every spacetime point—one might conjecture that settinginto sufficiently rapid rotation a finite mass concentration of appropriate shape will eventuate in CTCs. But with the goal in mind of proving negative general results, it is better to proceed in a more abstract fashion. Think of the conditions on the partial Cauchy surface (Sigma_0) as encoding the instructions for the operation of the time machine. The details of the operation of the device—whether it operates in a finite region of spacetime, whether it operates by setting matter into rotation, etc.—can be left to the side. What must be addressed, however, is whether the processes that evolve from the state on (Sigma_0) can be deemed to be responsible for the subsequent appearance of CTCs.
3. When can a would-be time machine be held responsible for the emergence of CTCs?
The most obvious move is to construe “responsible for” inthe sense of causal determinism. But in the present setting this movequickly runs into a dead end. For if CTCs exist to the future of (Sigma_0) they are not causally determined by the state on (Sigma_0) since the time travel region (V), if it isnon-null, lies outside the future domain of dependence (D^+ (Sigma_0)) of (Sigma_0), the portion of spacetime where the field equations of relativistic physics uniquely determine the state of things from the state on (Sigma_0).[12] The point is illustrated by the toy model of Figure 1. The surface labeled (H^+ (Sigma_0)) is called the future Cauchy horizon of (Sigma_0). It is the future boundary of (D^+ (Sigma_0)),[13] and it separates the portion of spacetime where conditions are causally determined by the state on (Sigma_0) from the portion where conditions are not so determined. And, as advertised, the CTCs in the model of Figure 1 lie beyond (H^+ (Sigma_0)).
Figure 2.Deutsch-Politzer spacetime
Thus, if the operation of a Thornian time machine is to be a live possibility, some condition weaker than causal determinism must be used to capture the sense in which the state on (Sigma_0) can be deemed to be responsible for the subsequent development of CTCs. Given the failure of causal determinism, it seems the next bestthing to demand that the region (V) is “adjacent” to the future domain of dependence (D^+ (Sigma_0)). Here is an initial stab at such an adjacency condition. Consider causal curves which have a future endpoint in the time travel region (V) and no past endpoint. Such a curve may never leave (V); but if it does, require that it intersects (Sigma_0). But this requirement is too strong because it rules out Thornian time machines altogether.For a curve of the type in question to reach (Sigma_0) it must intersect (H^+ (Sigma_0)), but once it reaches (H^+ (Sigma_0)) it can be continued endlessly into the past without meeting (Sigma_0)because the generators of (H^+ (Sigma_0))are past endless null geodesics that never meet (Sigma_0).[14] This difficulty can be overcome by weakening the requirement at issueby rephrasing it in terms of timelike curves rather than causal curves. Now the set of candidate time machine spacetimes satisfying the weakened requirement is non-empty—as illustrated, once again, by the spacetime of Figure 1. But the weakened requirement is too weak, as illustrated by the ((1 + 1))-dimensional version of Deutsch-Politzer spacetime[15] (see Figure 2), which is constructed from two-dimensional Minkowski spacetime by deleting the points (p_1)–(p_4) and then gluing together the strips as shown. Every past endless timelike curve that emerges from the time travel region (V) of Deutsch-Politzer spacetime does meet (Sigma_0). But this spacetime is not a plausible candidate for a time machine spacetime. Up to and includingthe time (Sigma_0) (which can be placed as close to (V) as desired) this spacetime is identical with empty Minkowski spacetime. If the state of the corresponding portion of Minkowski spacetime is not responsible for the development of CTCs—and it certainly is not since there are no CTCs in Minkowski spacetime—how can the state on the portion of Deutsch-Politzer spacetime up to and including the time (Sigma_0) be held responsible for the CTCs that appear in the future?
The deletion of the points (p_1)–(p_4) means that the Deutsch-Politzer spacetime is singular in the sense that it is geodesically incomplete.[16] It would be too drastic to require of a time-machine hosting spacetime that it be geodesically complete. And in any case the offending feature of Deutsch-Politzer can be gotten rid of by the following trick. Multiplying the flat Lorentzian metric (eta_{ab}) of Deutsch-Politzer spacetime by a scalarfunction (j(x, t) gt) produces a new metric (eta '_{ab} :=) j (eta_{ab}) which is conformal to the original metric and, thus, has exactly the same causal features as the original metric. But if the conformal factor (j) is chosen to “blow up” as the missing points (p_1)–(p_4) are approached, the resulting spacetime is geodesically complete—intuitively, the singularities have been pushed off to infinity.
A more subtle way to exclude Deutsch-Politzer spacetime focuses on the generators of (H^+ (Sigma_0)). The stipulations laid down so far for Thornian time machines imply that the generators of (H^+ (Sigma_0)) cannot intersect (Sigma_0). But in addition it can be required that these generators do not “emerge from a singularity” and do not “come from infinity,” and this would suffice to rule out Deutsch-Politzer spacetime and its conformal cousins as legitimate candidates for time machine spacetimes. More precisely, wecan impose what Stephen Hawking (1992a,b) calls the requirement that (H^+ (Sigma_0)) be compactly generated; namely, the past endless null geodesics that generate(H^+ (Sigma_0)) must, if extended far enough into past, fall into and remain in a compact subset of spacetime. Obviously the spacetime of Figure 1 fulfills Hawking’s requirement—since in this case (H^+ (Sigma_0)) is itself compact—but just as obviously the spacetime of Figure 2 (conformally doctored or not) does not.
Imposing the requirement of a compactly generated future Cauchy horizon has not only the negative virtue of excluding some unsuited candidate time machine spacetimes but a positive virtue as well. It is easily proved that if (H^+ (Sigma_0)) is compactly generated then the condition of strong causality is violated on (H^+ (Sigma_0)), which means, intuitively, there are almost closed causal curves near (H^+ (Sigma_0)).[17] This violation can be taken as an indication that the seeds of CTCs have been planted on (Sigma_0) and that by the time (H^+ (Sigma_0)) is reached they are readyto bloom.
However, we still have no guarantee that if CTCs do bloom to the future of (Sigma_0), then the state on (Sigma_0) is responsible for the blooming. Of course, we have already learned that we cannot have the iron clad guarantee of causal determinism that the state on (Sigma_0) is responsible for the actual blooming in all of its particularity. But we might hope for a guarantee that the state on (Sigma_0) is responsible for the blooming of some CTCs—the actual ones or others. The difference takes a bit of explaining. The failure of causal determinism is aptly pictured by the image of a future “branching” of world histories, with the different branches representing different alternative possible futures of (the domain of dependence of) (Sigma_0) that are compatible withthe actual past and the laws of physics. And so it is in the present setting: if (H^+ (Sigma_0) ne varnothing), then there will generally be different ways to extend (D^+ (Sigma_0)), all compatible with the laws of general relativistic physics. But if CTCs are present in all of these extensions, even through the details of the CTCs may vary from one extension to another, then the state on (Sigma_0) can rightly be deemed to be responsible for the fact that subsequently CTCs did develop.
A theorem due to Krasnikov (2002, 2003 [Other Internet Resources],2014a) might seem to demonstrate that no relativistic spacetime cancount as embodying a Thornian time machine so understood. FollowingKrasnikov, let us say that a spacetime condition (C)is local just in case, for any open covering({V_{alpha}}) of an arbitrary spacetime ((mathcal{M}, g_{ab}),C) holds in ((mathcal{M}, g_{ab})) iff it holds in ((V_{alpha},g_{ab}|_{V_{alpha}})) for all (alpha). Examples of localconditions one might want to impose on physically reasonablespacetimes are Einstein’s gravitational field equations andso-called energy conditions that restrict the form of thestress-energy tensor (T_{ab}). An example of the latter that willcome into play below is the weak energy condition that saysthat the energy density is non-negative.[18] Einstein’s field equations (sanscosmological constant) require that (T_{ab}) is proportional to theEinstein tensor which is a functional of the metric and itsderivatives. Call a (C)-spacetime ((mathcal{M}', g'_{ab})) a(C)-extension of a (C)-spacetime ((mathcal{M},g_{ab})) spacetime if the latter is isometric to an open propersubset of the former; and call ((mathcal{M}, g_{ab})C)-extensible if it admits a (C)-extension and(C)-maximal otherwise. (Of course, (C) might be the emptycondition.) Krasnikov’s theorem shows that every (C)-spacetime((mathcal{M}, g_{ab})) admits a (C)-maximal extension((mathcal{M}^{max}, g^{max}_{ab})) such that all CTCs in((mathcal{M}^{max}, g^{max}_{ab})) are to the chronological past ofthe image of (mathcal{M}) in ((mathcal{M}^{max},g^{max}_{ab})). So start with some candidate spacetime((mathcal{M}, g_{ab})) for a Thornian time machine, and apply thetheorem to ((D^+ (Sigma_0), g_{ab}|_{D^+ (Sigma_0)})). Concludethat no matter what local conditions the candidate spacetime isrequired to satisfy, (D^+ (Sigma_0)) has extensions that alsosatisfies said local conditions but does not contain CTCs to thefuture of (Sigma_0). Thus, the candidate spacetime fails to exhibitthe crucial feature identified above necessary for underwriting thecontention that the conditions on (Sigma_0) are responsible for thedevelopment of CTCs. Hence, it appears as if Krasnikov’stheorem effectively prohibits time machines.
The would-be time machine operator need not capitulate in the face ofKrasnikov’s theorem. Recall that the main difficulty inspecifying the conditions for the successful operation of Thorniantime machines traces to the fact that the standard form of causaldeterminism does not apply to the production of CTCs. But causaldeterminism can fail for reasons that have nothing to do with CTCs orother acausal features of relativistic spacetimes, and it seems onlyfair to ensure that these modes of failure have been removed beforeproceeding to discuss the prospects for time machines. To zero in onthe modes of failure at issue, consider vacuum solutions ((T_{ab}equiv 0)) to Einstein’s field equations. Let ((mathcal{M},g_{ab})) and ((mathcal{M}', g'_{ab})) be two such solutions, andlet (Sigma subset mathcal{M}) and (Sigma ' subsetmathcal{M}') be spacelike hypersurfaces of their respectivespacetimes. Suppose that there is an isometry (Psi) from someneighborhood (N(Sigma)) of (Sigma) onto a neighborhood(N'(Sigma ')) of (Sigma '). Does it follow, as we would wantdeterminism to guarantee, that (Psi) is extendible to an isometryfrom (D^+ (Sigma)) onto (D^+ (Sigma '))? To see why the answeris negative, start with any solution ((mathcal{M}, g_{ab})) of thevacuum Einstein equations, and cut out a closed set of points lying tothe future of (N(Sigma)) and in (D^+ (Sigma)). Denote thesurgically altered manifold by (mathcal{M}^*) and the restrictionof (g_{ab}) to (mathcal{M}^*) by (g^*_{ab}). Then((mathcal{M}^*, g^*_{ab})) is also a solution of the vacuumEinstein equations. But obviously the pair of solutions((mathcal{M}, g_{ab})) and ((mathcal{M}^*, g^*_{ab})) violatesthe condition that determinism was supposed to guarantee as (Psi)is not extendible to an isometry from (D^+ (Sigma)) onto (D^+(Sigma^*)). It might seem that the requirement, contemplated above,that the spacetimes under consideration be maximal, already rules outspacetimes that have “holes” in them. But while maximalitydoes rule out the surgically mutilated spacetime just constructed, itdoes not guarantee hole freeness in the sense needed to make sure thatdeterminism does not stumble before it gets to the starting gate.That ((mathcal{M}, g_{ab})) is hole free in the relevant senserequires that if (Sigma subset mathcal{M}) is a spacelikehypersurface, there does not exist a spacetime ((mathcal{M}',g'_{ab})) and an isometric embedding (Phi) of (D^+ (Sigma))into (mathcal{M}') such that (Phi(D^+ (Sigma))) is a propersubset of (D^+ (Phi(Sigma))). A theorem due to Robert Geroch(1977, 87), who is responsible for this definition, asserts that if(Sigma subset mathcal{M}) and (Sigma ' subset mathcal{M}')are spacelike hypersurfaces in hole-free spacetimes ((mathcal{M},g_{ab})) and ((mathcal{M}', g'_{ab})), respectively, and if thereexists an isometry (Psi : mathcal{M} rightarrow mathcal{M}'),then (Psi) is indeed extendible to an isometry between (D^+(Sigma)) and (D^+ (Sigma ')). Thus, hole freeness precludes animportant mode of failure of determinism which we wish to exclude inour discussion of time machines. It can be shown that hole freeness isnot entailed by maximality.[19] And it is just this gap that gives thewould-be time machine operator some hope, for the maximal CTC-freeextensions produced by Krasnikov’s construction are not alwayshole free (Manchak 2009b). But Krasnikov (2009) has shown that theGeroch (1977) definition is too strong: Minkowski spacetime fails tosatisfy it! For this reason, alternative formulations of thehole-freeness definition have been constructed which are moreappropriate (Manchak 2009a, Minguzzi 2012).
Thus, we propose that one clear sense of what it would mean for aThornian time machine to operate in the setting of general relativitytheory is given by the following assertion: the laws of generalrelativistic physics allow solutions containing a partial Cauchysurface (Sigma_0) such that no CTCs lie to the past of(Sigma_0) but every extension of(D^+ (Sigma_0)) satisfying ________contains CTCs (where the blank is filled with some “nohole” condition). Correspondingly, a proof of the physicalimpossibility of time machines would take the form of showing thatthis assertion is false for the actual laws of physics, consisting,presumably, of Einstein’s field equations plus energy conditions and,perhaps, some additional restrictions as well. And a proof of theemptiness of the associated concept of a Thornian time machine wouldtake the form of showing that the assertion is false independently ofthe details of the laws of physics, as long as they take the form oflocal conditions on (T_{ab}) and (g_{ab}).
Are there 'no hole' conditions which show the proposed concept of a time machine is not empty? Let (J^+(p)) designate the causal future of (p), defined as the set of all points in (mathcal{M}) which can be reached from (p) by a future-directed causal curve in (mathcal{M}). The causal past (J^-(p)) is defined analogously. Now, we say a spacetime ((mathcal{M},g_{ab})) is J closed if, for each (p) in (mathcal{M}), the sets (J^+(p)) and (J^-(p)) are topologically closed. One can verify that J closedness fails in many artificially mutilated examples (e.g. Minkowski spacetime with one point removed from the manifold). For some time, it was thought that a time machine existed under this no-hole condition (Manchak 2011a). But this turns out to be incorrect; indeed a recent result shows that any J closed spacetime ((mathcal{M},g_{ab})) of three dimensions or more with chronology violating region (V neq mathcal{M}) must be strongly causal and therefore fail to have CTCs (Hounnonkpe and Minguzzi 2019). Stepping back, perhaps there are other no-hole conditions which can be used instead to show that the proposed concept of a time machine is not empty. But even if such a project were successful, Manchak (2014a, 2019) has shown that the time machine existence results can benaturally reinterpreted as “hole machine” existence results if one is so inclined. Instead of assuming that spacetime isfree of holes and then showing that certain initial conditions areresponsible for the production of CTCs, one could just as well startwith the assumption of no CTCs and then show that certain initialconditions are responsible for the production of holes. Given theimportance of these no hole assumptions to the time machine advocate,much recent work has focused on whether such assumptions arephysically reasonable in some sense (Manchak 2011b,2014b). This is still an open question.
Another open question is whether physically more realistic spacetimesthan Misner also permit the operation of time machines and how generictime-machine spacetimes are in particular spacetime theories, such asgeneral relativity. If time-machine spacetimes turn out to be highlynon-generic, the fan of time machines can retreat to a weaker conceptof Thornian time machine by taking a page from probabilistic accountsof causation, the idea being that a time machine can be seen to be atwork if its operation increases the probability of the appearance ofCTCs. Since general relativity theory itself is innocent ofprobabilities, they have to be introduced by hand, either by insertingthem into the models of the theory, i.e., by modifying the theory atthe level of the object-language, or by defining measures on sets ofmodels, i.e., by modifying the theory at the level of themeta-language. Since the former would change the character of thetheory, only the latter will be considered. The project for makingsense of the notion that a time machine as a probabilistic cause ofthe appearance of CTCs would then take the following form. Firstdefine a normalized measure on the set of models having a partialCauchy surface to the past of which there are no CTCs. Then show thatthe subset of models that have CTCs to the future of the partialCauchy surface has non-zero measure. Next, identify a range ofconditions on or near the partial Cauchy surface that are naturallyconstrued as settings of a device that is a would-be probabilisticcause of CTCs, and show that the subset of models satisfying theseconditions has non-zero measure. Finally, show that conditionalizingon the latter subset increases the measure of the formersubset. Assuming that this formal exercise can be successfully carriedout, there remains the task of justifying these as measures ofobjective chance. This task is especially daunting in the cosmologicalsetting since neither of the leading interpretations of objectivechance seems applicable. The frequency interpretation is strainedsince the development of CTCs may be a non-repeated phenomenon; andthe propensity interpretation is equally strained since, barringjust-so stories about the Creator throwing darts at the Cosmic DartBoard, there is no chance mechanism for producing cosmologicalmodels.
We conclude that, even apart from general doubts about a probabilistic account of causation, the resort to a probabilistic conception of time machines is a desperate stretch, at least in the context of classical general relativity theory. In a quantum theory of gravity, a probabilistic conception of time machines may be appropriate if the theory itself provides the transition probabilities between the relevant states. But an evaluation of this prospect must wait until the theory of quantum gravity is available.
4. No-go results for (Thornian) time machines in classical general relativity theory
In order to appreciate the physics literature aimed at proving no-go results for time machines it is helpful to view these efforts as partof the broader project of proving chronology protections theorems, which in turn is part of a still larger project of proving cosmic censorship theorems. To explain, we start with cosmic censorship and work backwards.
For sake of simplicity, concentrate on the initial value problem for vacuum solutions ((T_{ab} equiv 0)) to Einstein’s field equations. Start with a three-manifold (Sigma) equipped with quantities which, when (Sigma) is embedded as a spacelike submanifoldof spacetime, become initial data for the vacuum field equations. Corresponding to the initial data there exists a unique[20] maximal development ((mathcal{M}, g_{ab})) for which (the image of the embedded) (Sigma) is a Cauchy surface.[21] This solution, however, may not be maximal simpliciter, i.e., it may be possible to isometrically embed it as a proper part of a larger spacetime, which itself may be a vacuum solution to the field equations; if so (Sigma) will not be a Cauchy surface for the extended spacetime, which fails to be a globally hyperbolic spacetime.[22] This situation can arise because of a poor choice of initial value hypersurface, as illustrated in Figure 3 by taking (Sigma) to be the indicated spacelike hyperboloid of ((1 + 1))-dimensional Minkowski spacetime. But, more interestingly, the situation can arise because the Einstein equations allow various pathologies, collectively referred to as “naked singularities,” to develop from regular initial data. The strong form of Penrose’s celebrated cosmic censorship conjecture proposes that, consistent with Einstein’s field equations, such pathologies do not arise under physically reasonable conditions or else that the conditions leading to the pathologies arehighly non-generic within the space of all solutions to the field equations. A small amount of progress has been made on stating and proving precise versions of this conjecture.[23]
One way in which strong cosmic censorship can be violated is through the emergence of acausal features. Returning to the example of Misnerspacetime (Figure 1), the spacetime up to (H^+ (Sigma_0)) is the unique maximal development of the vacuum Einstein equations for which (Sigma_0) is a Cauchy surface. But this development is extendible, and in the extension illustrated in Figure 1 global hyperbolicity of the development is lost because of the presence of CTCs. The chronology protection conjecture then can be construed as a subconjecture of the cosmic censorship conjecture, saying, roughly, that consistent with Einstein field equations, CTCs do not arise under physically reasonable conditions or else that the conditions are highly non-generic within the space of all solutions to the field equations. No-go results for time machines are then special forms of chronology protection theorems that deal with cases where the CTCs are manufactured by time machines. In the other direction, a very general chronology protection theorem will automatically provide a no-go result for timemachines, however that notion is understood, and a theorem establishing strong cosmic censorship will automatically impose chronology protection.
The most widely discussed chronology protection theorem/no-go result for time machines in the context of classical general relativity theory is due to Hawking (1992a). Before stating the result, note first that, independently of the Einstein field equations and energy conditions, a partial Cauchy surface (Sigma) must be compact if its future Cauchy horizon (H^+ (Sigma)) is compact (seeHawking 1992a and Chrusciel and Isenberg 1993). However, it is geometrically allowed that (Sigma) is non-compact if (H^+ (Sigma)) is required only to be compactly generated rather than compact. But what Hawking showed is that this geometrical possibility is ruled out by imposing Einstein’s field equations and the weak energy condition. Thus, if (Sigma_0)is a partial Cauchy surface representing the situation just before orjust as the would-be Thornian time machine is switched on, and if a necessary condition for seeing a Thornian time machine at work is that (H^+ (Sigma_0)) is compactly generated, then consistently with Einstein’s field equations and the weak energy condition, a Thornian time machine cannot operate in a spatially open universe since (Sigma_0) must be compact.
This no-go result does not touch the situation illustrated in Figure 1. Taub-NUT spacetime is a vacuum solution to Einstein’s field equationsso the weak energy condition is automatically satisfied, and (H^+ (Sigma_0)) is compact and, a fortiori, compactly generated. Hawking’s theorem is not contradicted since (Sigma_0) is compact. By the same token the theorem does not speak to the possibility of operating a Thornian time machine in a spatially closed universe. To help fill the gap, Hawkingproved that when (Sigma_0) is compact and (H^+ (Sigma_0)) is compactly generated, the Einstein field equations and the weak energy condition together guarantee that both the convergence and shear of the null geodesic generators of (H^+ (Sigma_0)) must vanish, which he interpreted to imply that no observers can cross over (H^+ (Sigma_0)) to enter the chronology violating region (V). But rather than showing that it is physically impossible to operate a Thornian time machine in a closed universe, this result shows only that, given the correctness of Hawking’s interpretation, the observers who operate the time machine cannot take advantage of the CTCs it produces.
There are two sources of doubt about the effectiveness of Hawking’s no-go result even for open universes. The first stems from possible violations of the weak energy condition by stress-energy tensors arising from classical relativistic matter fields (see Vollick 1997 and Visser and Barcelo 2000).[24] The second stems from the fact that Hawking’s theorem functions as a chronology protection theorem only by way of serving as a potential no-go result for Thornian time machines since the crucial condition that (H^+ (Sigma_0)) is compactly generated is supposedly justified by being a necessary condition for the operation of such machine. But in retrospect, the motivation for this condition seems frayed. As argued in the previous section, if the Einstein field equations and energy conditions entail that all hole free extensions of (D^+ (Sigma_0)) contain CTCs, then it is plausible to see a Thornian time machine at work, quite regardless ofwhether or not (H^+ (Sigma_0)) is compactly generated ornot. Of course, it remains to establish the existence of cases where this entailment holds. If it should turn out that there are no such cases, then the prospects of Thornian time machines are dealt a severe blow, but the reasons are independent of Hawking’s theorem. Onthe other hand, if such cases do exist then our conjecture would be that they exist even when some of the generators of (H^+ (Sigma_0)) come from singularities or infinity and, thus, (H^+ (Sigma_0)) isnot compactly generated.[25]
5. No-go results in quantum gravity
Time Machine Roblox
Three degrees of quantum involvement in gravity can be distinguished.The first degree, referred to as quantum field theory on curved spacetimes, simply takes off the shelf a spacetime provided by general relativity theory and then proceeds to study the behavior of quantum fields on this background spacetime. The Unruh effect, which predicts the thermalization of a free scalar quantum field near the horizon of a black hole, lies within this ambit. The second degree ofinvolvement, referred to as semi-classical quantum gravity, attempts to calculate the backreaction of the quantum fields on spacetime metric by computing the expectation value (langle Psi mid T_{ab} mid Psi rangle) of the stress-energy tensor in some appropriate quantum state (lvertPsirangle) and then inserting the value into Einstein’s field equations in place of (T_{ab}).[26] Hawking’s celebrated prediction of black hole radiation belongs to this ambit.[27] The third degree of involvement attempts to produce a genuine quantumtheory of gravity in the sense that the gravitational degrees of freedom are quantized. Currently loop quantum gravity and string theory are the main research programs aimed at this goal.[28]
Time Machine Lyrics
The first degree of quantum involvement, if not opening the door to Thornian time machines, at least seemed to remove some obstacles since quantum fields are known to lead to violations of the energy conditions used in the setting of classical general relativity theoryto prove chronology protection theorems and no-go results for time machines. However, the second degree of quantum involvement seemed, at least initially, to slam the door shut. The intuitive idea was this. Start with a general relativistic spacetime where CTCs develop to the future of (H^+ (Sigma)) (often referred to as the “chronology horizon”) for some suitable partial Cauchy surface (Sigma). Find that the propagation of a quantum field on this spacetime background is such that (langle Psi mid T_{ab} midPsi rangle) “blows up” as(H^+ (Sigma)) is approached from the past. Concludethat the backreaction on the spacetime metric creates unbounded curvature, which effectively cuts off the future development that would otherwise eventuate in CTCs. These intuitions were partly vindicated by detailed calculations in several models. But eventuallya number of exceptions were found in which the backreaction remains arbitrarily small near (H^+ (Sigma)).[29] This seemed to leave the door ajar for Thornian time machines.
But fortunes were reversed once again by a result of Kay, Radzikowski, and Wald (1997). The details of their theorem are too technical to review here, but the structure of the argument is easy to grasp. The naïve calculation of (langle Psi mid T_{ab}midPsi rangle) results in infinities which have to be subtracted off to produce a renormalized expectationvalue (langle Psi mid T_{ab}midPsi rangle_R) witha finite value. The standard renormalization procedure uses a limiting procedure that is mathematically well-defined if, and only if, a certain condition obtains.[30] The KRW theorem shows that this condition is violated for points on (H^+ (Sigma)) and, thus, that the expectation valueof the stress-energy tensor is not well-defined at the chronology horizon.
Time Machine 1 Hour
While the KRW theorem is undoubtedly of fundamental importance for semi-classical quantum gravity, it does not serve as an effective no-go result for Thornian time machines. In the first place, the theorem assumes, in concert with Hawking’s chronology protection theorem, that (H^+ (Sigma)) is compactly generated,and we repeat that it is far from clear that this assumption is necessary for seeing a Thornian time machine in operation. A second, and more fundamental, reservation applies even if a compactly generated (H^+ (Sigma)) is accepted as a necessary condition for time machines. The KRW theorem functions as a no-go result by providing a reductio ad absurdum with a dubious absurdity: roughly, if you try to operate a Thornian time machine, you will end up invalidating semi-classical quantum gravity. But semi-classical quantum gravity was never viewed as anything more thana stepping stone to a genuine quantum theory of gravity, and its breakdown is expected to be manifested when Planck-scale physics comes into play. This worry is underscored by Visser’s (1997, 2003) findings that in chronology violating models trans-Planckian physics can be expected to come into play before (H^+ (Sigma)) is reached.
It thus seems that if some quantum mechanism is to serve as the basisfor chronology protection, it must be found in the third degree of quantum involvement in gravity. Both loop quantum gravity and string theory have demonstrated the ability to cure some of the curvature singularities of classical general relativity theory. But as far as we are aware there are no demonstrations that either of these approaches to quantum gravity can get rid of the acausal features exhibited in various solutions to Einstein’s field equations. An alternative approach to formulate a fully-fledged quantum theory of gravity attempts to capture the Planck-scale structure of spacetime by constructing it from causal sets.[31] Since these sets must be acyclic, i.e., no element in a causal set can causally precede itself, CTCs are ruled out a priori. Actually, atheorem due to Malament (1977) suggests that any Planck-scale approach encoding only the causal structure of a spacetime cannot permit CTCs either in the smooth classical spacetimes or a corresponding phenomenon in their quantum counterparts.[32]
In sum, the existing no-go results that use the first two degrees of quantum involvement are not very convincing, and the third degree of involvement is not mature enough to allow useful pronouncements. There is, however, a rapidly growing literature on the possibility oftime travel in lower-dimensional supersymmetric cousins of string theory. For a review of these recent results and a discussion of the fate of a time-traveller’s ambition in loop quantum gravity, see Smeenk and Wüthrich (2010).
6. Conclusion
Hawking opined that “[i]t seems there is a chronology protection agency, which prevents the appearance of closed timelike curves and so makes the universe safe for historians” (1992a, 603). He may be right, but to date there are no convincing arguments that such an Agency is housed in either classical general relativity theory or in semi-classical quantum gravity. And it is too early to tell whether this Agency is housed in loop quantum gravity or string theory. But even if it should turn out that Hawking is wrong in that the laws of physics do not support a Chronology Protection Agency, itcould still be the case that the laws support an Anti-Time Machine Agency. For it could turn out that while the laws do not prevent the development of CTCs, they also do not make it possible to attribute the appearance of CTCs to the workings of any would-be time machine. We argued that a strong presumption in favor of the latter would be created in classical general relativity theory by the demonstration that for any model satisfying Einstein’s field equations and energy conditions as well as possessing a partial Cauchy surface (Sigma_0) to the future of which there are CTCs, there are hole free extensions of (D^+ (Sigma_0)) satisfying Einstein’s field equations and energy conditions but containing no CTCs to the future of (Sigma_0). There are no doubt alternative approaches tounderstanding what it means for a device to be “responsible for” the development of CTCs. Exploring these alternatives is one place that philosophers can hope to make a contribution to an ongoing discussion that, to date, has been carried mainly by the physics community. Participating in this discussion means that philosophers have to forsake the activity of logical gymnastics with the paradoxes of time travel for the more arduous but (we believe) rewarding activity of digging into the foundations of physics.
Time machines may never see daylight, and perhaps so for principled reasons that stem from basic physical laws. But even if mathematical theorems in the various theories concerned succeed in establishing the impossibility of time machines, understanding why time machines cannot be constructed will shed light on central problems in the foundations of physics. As we have argued in Section 4, for instance,the hunt for time machines in general relativity theory should be interpreted as a core issue in studying the fortunes of Penrose’s cosmic censorship conjecture. This conjecture arguably constitutes the most important open problem in general relativity theory. Similarly, as discussed in Section 5, mathematical theorems related to various aspects of time machines offer results relevant for the search of a quantum theory of gravity. In sum, studying the possibilities for operating a time machine turns out to be not a scientifically peripheral or frivolous weekend activity but a useful way of probing the foundations of classical and quantum theories of gravity.
Bibliography
- Arntzenius, F. and T. Maudlin, 2009, “Time Travel and ModernPhysics,” in E.N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia ofPhilosophy (Spring 2009Edition), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2009/entries/time-travel-phys/>.
- Brightwell, G., H.F. Dowker, R.S. Garcia, J. Henson, andR.D. Sorkin, 2003, “‘Observables’ in causal setcosmology,” Physical Review D, 67:08403. [Preprint available online.]
- Callender, C., 2001, “Thermodynamic Asymmetry inTime,” in E.N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia ofPhilosophy (Spring 2001 Edition), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2001/entries/time-thermo/>.
- Chrusciel, P.T. and J. Isenberg, 1993, “Compact CauchyHorizons and Cauchy Surfaces,” in B.L. Hu and T.A. Jacobson(eds.), Papers in Honor of Dieter Brill: Directions in GeneralRelativity (Volume 2), Cambridge: Cambridge UniversityPress, pp. 97–107.
- Davies, P., 2002a, How to Build a Time Machine, London:Viking Penguin.
- –––, 2002b, “How to Build a TimeMachine,” Scientific American, 287(3): 50–55.
- Deutsch, D., 1991, “Quantum Mechanics Near Closed TimelikeLines,” Physical Review D, 44: 3197–3217.
- Earman, J., 1995a, Bangs, Crunches, Whimpers, and Shrieks:Singularities and Acausalities in Relativistic Spacetimes, NewYork: Oxford University Press.
- –––, 1995b, “Recent Work on Time Travel,” inS.F. Savitt (ed.), Time’s Arrow Today: Recent Physical andPhilosophical Work on the Direction of Time,Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 268–310.
- –––, 1995c, “Outlawing Time Machines: ChronologyProtection Theorems,” Erkenntnis, 42: 125–139.
- –––, 1999, “The Penrose-HawkingSingularity Theorems: History and Implications,” in H. Goenner,J. Renn, and T. Sauer (eds.), The Expanding Worlds of GeneralRelativity, Einstein Studies, Vol. 7, Boston: Birkhäuser,pp. 235–267.
- Earman, J., C. Smeenk, and C. Wüthrich, 2009, “Do theLaws of Physics Forbid the Operation of TimeMachines?” Synthese, 169: 91–124. [Preprint available online]
- Geroch, R., 1977, “Prediction in General Relativity,”in J. Earman, C. Glymour, and J. Stachel (eds.), Foundations ofSpacetime Theories (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy ofScience: Volume VIII), Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press,pp. 81–93.
- Gott, R., 2001, Time Travel in Einstein’s Universe, NewYork: Houghton Mifflin.
- Greene, B., 2003, The Elegant Universe, New York:W. W. Norton.
- Hawking, S.W., 1992a, “Chronology ProtectionConjecture,” Physical Review D, 46: 603–611.
- –––, 1992b, “The Chronology ProtectionConjecture,” in H. Sato and T. Nakamura (eds.), Proceedingsof the Sixth Marcel Grossmann Meeting on General Relativity,Singapore: World Scientific, pp. 3–13.
- –––, 2001, “Chronology Protection: Making theWorld Safe for Historians,” in S.W. Hawking etal. (eds.), The Future of Spacetime, New York:W.W. Norton, pp. 87–108.
- Hawking, S.W. and G.F.R. Ellis, 1973, The Large ScaleStructure of Space-Time, Cambridge: Cambridge UniversityPress.
- Hawking, S.W. and R. Penrose, 1970, “The Singularities ofGravitational Collapse and Cosmology,” Proceedings of theRoyal Society of London A, 314: 529–548.
- Hoefer, C., 2003, “Causal Determinism,” in E.N. Zalta(ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2003Edition), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2003/entries/determinism-causal/>.
- Hounnonkpe, R.A. and E. Minguzzi, 2019, “Globally Hyperbolic Spacetimes Can Be Defined Without the ‘Causal’ Condition,” Classical and Quantum Gravity, 36: 197001.
- Kay, B.S., M.J. Radzikowski, and R.M. Wald, 1997, “QuantumField Theory On Spacetimes with Compactly Generated CauchyHorizons,” Communications in Mathematical Physics, 183:533–556.
- Keller, S. and M. Nelson, 2001, “Presentists Should Believein Time-Travel,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy,79: 333–345.
- Krasnikov, S., 1999, “Time Machines with Non-CompactlyGenerated Cauchy Horizons and ‘HandySingularities’,” in T. Piran and R. Ruffini(eds.), Proceedings of the Eighth Marcel Grossmann Meeting onGeneral Relativity, Singapore: WorldScientific, pp. 593–595. [Preprint available online.]
- –––, 2002, “No Time Machines in Classical GeneralRelativity,” Classical and Quantum Gravity, 19:4109–4129. [Preprint available online.]
- –––, 2009, “Even the Minkowski space isholed.” Physical Review D, 79: 124041.
- –––, 2014a, “Corrigendum: No Time machines inClassical General Relativity,” Classical and QuantumGravity, 31: 079503.
- –––, 2014b, “Time Machines with the CompactlyDetermined Cauchy Horizon,” Physical Review D, 90:024067. [Preprint available online.]
- Malament, D.B., 1977, “The class of continuous timelikecurves determines the topology of spacetime,” Journal ofMathematical Physics, 18: 1399–1404.
- Manchak, J.B., 2009a, “Is SpacetimeHole-Free?’ General Relativity and Gravitation, 41:1639–1643
- –––, 2009b, “On the Existence of‘Time Machines,” in GeneralRelativity,” Philosophy of Science, 76: 1020–1026.
- –––, 2011a, “No no-go: A remark on timemachines,”Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 42:74–76.
- –––, 2011b, “What is a PhysicallyReasonable Space-Time?” Philosophy of Science, 78:410–420.
- –––, 2014a, “Time (hole?) machines,”Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 48:124–127.
- –––, 2014b, “On Space-Time Singularities,Holes, and Extensions,” Philosophy of Science, 81:1066–1076.
- –––, 2019, “A Remark on ‘TimeMachines’ in Honor of Howard Stein,” Studies inHistory and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 67: 111–116.
- Minguzzi, E., 2012, “Causally Simple Inextendible Spacetimesare Hole-Free,” Journal of Mathematical Physics, 53:062501.
- Monton, B., 2003, “Presentists Can Believe in ClosedTimelike Curves,” Analysis, 63: 199–202.
- Morris, M.S. and K.S. Thorne, 1988, “Wormholes in Spacetimeand Their Use for Interstellar Travel: A Tool for Teaching GeneralRelativity,” American Journal of Physics, 56:395-412.
- Morris, M.S., K.S. Thorne, and U. Yurtsever, 1988,“Wormholes, Time Machines, and the Weak EnergyCondition,” Physical Review Letters, 61:1446-1449.
- Nahin, P.J., 1999, Time Machines: Time Travel in Physics,Metaphysics, and Science Fiction, New York: AIP Press,Springer.
- Norton, J., 2008, “The Hole Argument,” in E.N. Zalta(ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2008Edition), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2008/entries/spacetime-holearg/>.
- Ori, A., 1993, “Must Time-Machine Construction Violate theWeak Energy Condition?” Physical Review Letters, 71:2517-2520.
- Politzer, H.D., 1992, “Simple Quantum Systems in Spacetimeswith Closed Timelike Curves,” Physical Review D, 46:4470–4476.
- Rovelli, C., 2004, Quantum Gravity, Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.
- Smeenk, C. and C. Wüthrich, 2010, “Time Travel and TimeMachines”, forthcoming in C. Callender (ed.), The OxfordHandbook of Time, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Visser, M., 1997, “The Reliability Horizon forSemi-Classical Quantum Gravity: Metric Fluctuations Are Often MoreImportant than Back-Reaction,” Physics Letters B, 115:8-14.
- –––, 2003, “The Quantum Physics of ChronologyProtection,” in G.W. Gibbons, E.P.S. Shellard, S.J. Rankin(eds.), The Future of Theoretical Physics and Cosmology:Celebrating Stephen Hawking’s 60th Birthday,Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 161–176.
- Visser, M. and C. Barcelo, 2000, “Energy conditions andtheir cosmological implications,” in U. Cotti, R. Jeannerot,G. Senjanović, and A. Smirnov (eds.),Proceedings of the Third International Workshop onParticle Physics and the Early Universe (COSMO-99), Singapore: World Scientific, pp. 99–112. [Preprint available online.]
- Vollick, D.N., 1997, “How to Produce Exotic Matter UsingClassical Fields,” Physical Review D, 56:4720–4723.
- Wald, R.M., 1984, General Relativity, Chicago: Universityof Chicago Press.
- –––, 1994, Quantum Field Theory in Curved Spacetime andBlack Hole Thermodynamics, Chicago: University of ChicagoPress.
- –––, 1998, “Gravitational Collapse and CosmicCensorship,” in B.R. Iyer, and B. Bhawal (eds.), BlackHoles, Gravitational Radiation and the Universe: Essays in Honor ofC. V. Vishveshwara, Dordrecht: Kluwer AcademicPublishers, pp. 69–85. [Preprint available online.]
- Wells, H.G., 1931, The Time Machine, New York: RandomHouse.
- Zwiebach, B., 2004, A First Course on StringTheory, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Academic Tools
How to cite this entry. |
Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society. |
Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). |
Enhanced bibliography for this entryat PhilPapers, with links to its database. |
Other Internet Resources
- Krasnikov, S., 2003, “Time Machine (1988-2001),” a brief account of the time machine problem;talk given at 11th U.K. Conference on the Foundations of Physics,Oxford, England, 9-13, Sept. 2002.
- Rovelli, C., 1998, “Loop Quantum Gravity”, in Living Reviews in Relativity.
Related Entries
determinism: causal | space and time: the hole argument | time: thermodynamic asymmetry in | time travel | time travel: and modern physics
Acknowledgments
We thank Carlo Rovelli for discussions and John Norton for comments on an earlier draft. C.W. acknowledges support by the Swiss National Science Foundation (grant PBSK1-102693).
Copyright © 2020 by
John Earman<jearman@pitt.edu>
Christian Wüthrich<christian.wuthrich@unige.ch>
JB Manchak<jmanchak@uci.edu>